Predestination and the Metaphysics of Identity: A Yoruba (African) Case Study

 

Predestination and the Metaphysics of Identity: A Yoruba (African) Case Study

Yunusa Kehinde Salami

Credit: Prof L. O. Adewole
Yoruba for academic purpose


Abstract

Predestination, as a metaphysical issue, carries the idea of prenatal choice or ascription of the purpose or end to which any person or thing is created. Destiny, as chosen by or ascribed to a person represents what the person has to unwind in the world. In Yoruba account of predestination, a moulded body, already infused with the spirit of life by Olodumare (the supreme being), goes to pick an Orí (the bearer of destiny). Sometimes, such a destiny is considered imposed on the self. The destiny, so chosen or so ascribed or imposed, encapsulates the successes and failures which the human being is meant to unravel during his or her course of existence in this world.
           Considering some arguments on the metaphysical question of personal identity, the paper observes that it will be difficult to establish a case of personal  identity between the person who chose a destiny in ìsálú ọ̀run (heavenly abode) and the one who is assumed to be unravelling it in this ìsálú ayé (earthly world). The paper concludes that it will be difficult to establish a case for predestination if a relationship of identity cannot be easily established between the two entities.

Introduction
Predestination, as a metaphysical issue, carries the idea of prenatal choice or an ascription of purpose or end to which any person or thing is created. Destiny as chosen by or ascribed to a person represents what the person has to unwind in this world. In Yoruba account of predestination, a moulded body, already infused with the spirit of life by Olódùmarè, goes to pick an Orí (the bearer of destiny). Sometimes, such a destiny or Orí is considered imposed on the self. The destiny, so chosen or so ascribed or imposed, encapsulates the successes and failures which the human being is meant to unravel during his or her course of existence in this world. 
         The question may be raised concerning the identity of the being that chose a destiny or upon whom a destiny was imposed in heaven, and the human being, on earth, who is expected to manifest or actualise the destiny. Unless the relationship of identity can be established between the two entities, it may be difficult, if at all, to talk of predestination.
            Given some arguments on personal identity, it seems problematic to establish the position that a specific human being was prenatally destined to do some things and not others while on earth. The interest of this paper is to examine the possibility of identity between the person who is acclaimed to have chosen a destiny in heaven and the one who is saddled with the responsibility of unravelling the destiny on earth.

 

Yoruba Account of Predestination 

In the Yoruba conception of human person[i], a human person is made of ara, ẹ̀mí and orí. Ara is body, ẹ̀mi is soul while orí is the inner head.  Orí (the inner head) is regarded as the bearer of destiny. This account of human person emphasizes the importance of ori and by implication, makes destiny or predestination a necessary component of a human person. With this introduction of ‘orí’, the third component, there is a challenge to the Cartesian dualist account of human person. This gives a tripartite conception of human person as against the dualist account of Descartes.
           Yoruba generally refer to ori as the unconscious self, as inner head, as one’s guardian spirit, and as the bearer of destiny. According to Gbadegesin, “…it is the ori that selects the destiny of the person before Olódùmarè (the Supreme deity) who normally endorses such a choice”[ii].  Another account of Yoruba concept of ori ́is given by Idowu, who claims that Yoruba regard orí as the personality Spirit. For Idowu, orí “is the very essence of personality…it is this orí that rules, controls, and guides the ‘life’ and activities of the person”[iii].  Going by Idowu and other available materials on orí and destiny, a person’s destiny can be known as ìpín-orí or shortened. This can be translated as the orí’s portion or lot. Ìpín means portion, and orí means the inner head. So, ìpín orí means ori’s portion or lot.
             The question, however, is about the status of orí vis-à-vis other causal agents. Can we regard orí as the antecedent cause of all other possible causes? In other words, do we see other causes as mere causal manifestations of one underlying cause - orí? If the answer is yes, then we can correctly argue that there is a connection between the Yoruba concept of orí and destiny. This takes us to the other related Yoruba notions of ìpín (that which is allocated to someone), àyànmọ́ (that which is affixed to someone), and àkúnlẹ̀yàn (that which is chosen kneeling). All of these concepts convey the idea of destiny which, if critically examined, could be seen to convey some important differences. For Idowu, “… we have a trimophous conception of destiny.”[iv]
            Going by these related terms, a little clarification may be warranted. For instance, àyànmọ́ and ìpín imply something that was imposed on human persons, without any enquiry on whether they wanted it or not. Àyànmọ́ and ìpín are predominantly suggestive of the influence of an external factor against which we are powerless. Consequently, one may, it seems to me, argue that what becomes one’s destiny is not within one’s ability to choose. Given this account, the action one finds oneself performing here on earth, is independent of one’s choice or wishes in this world. The account renders human beings as mere toys in the hands of the gods. On the other hand, àkúnlẹ̀yàn is suggestive of one’s conscious choice, most probably, without any external compulsion. In spite of these differences in Yoruba conceptions of predestination, a person comes into the world with his destiny doubly sealed, and whatever a person does achieve, or whatever happens to him, is a precise working out of his destiny. [v]
             The upshot of this is that in Yoruba universe, each human being is predestined to lead a kind of life and not others. That is, each human being while in ìsálú ọ̀run (heavenly abode), chose or found affixed on him or her, a particular kind of destiny which he or she is expected to actualise, unravel, or manifest in this ìsálú ayé (earthly world). On this account, destiny represents the kind of choice or affixation in ìsálú ọ̀run which will invariably determine the earthly success or failure. It is believed that the choice or affixation of a good orí ensures that the individual concerned would lead a successful and prosperous life on earth, while the choice or affixation of a bad orí condemns the individual concerned to a life of failure.[vi]

 

 Yoruba Account of Predestination and Problem of Personal Identity

The problem of ‘Personal identity’ arose because a human person is not stationary either in space or in time. Many a time, when a person exists at any particular time and space, we also consider him or her with himself or herself at an earlier or later time and space. When we see anyone at a particular space and time, it is always clear to us that he is himself and not another person who at the same time exists at the same time in another place, whatever feature they share in common. In this case, ‘Personal identity’ invokes a relation between a person who is known to exist at one time, and a person who is known to have existed at another time.[vii] Identity in this sense presupposes “an uninterrupted continuance of existence”[viii]. The reasoning here according to Reid, is that;

 that which has ceased to exist cannot be the same with that which afterward begins to exist; for this would be to suppose a being to exist after it ceased to exist, and to have had existence before it was produced.[ix]

The point now is that given the problem of personal identity, questions can be raised about the identity between the entity that chose a destiny or upon whom a destiny was imposed in heaven and the entity that is unravelling this destiny here on earth. For instance, it will interest philosophers to know whether the figure who picked a destiny or upon whom a destiny was affixed at ìsálú ọ̀run is the same person as, or, identical to, the human being who is in this ìsálú ayé unravelling the earlier chosen or affixed destiny. Can a case of uninterrupted continual existence be established between the two entities?
          It is important to note that unless there is an identity between the body which chose a destiny, or on which a destiny was affixed, and the person whose life manifests the destiny, it will be difficult, if not impossible, to talk of predestination and the later unravelling of such a destiny. My point is that if there is actually no identity or sameness, the talk of destiny or predestination becomes otiose. This takes us to the discussion on what the idea of personal identity entails. In other words, what properties or qualities should be obtained in order to establish personal identity?
                Philosophers have variously attempted to tackle the problem of personal identity. The problem of personal identity, like all other metaphysical problems, has almost been intractable. While most philosophers tend to agree that personal identity involves an uninterrupted continual existence, they differ on what it is that uninterruptedly continues to exist. What each philosopher takes as the subject of uninterrupted continual existence depends largely on his or her general metaphysical standpoint on the question of the ultimate constituent of personhood.
               While for some, mind or soul (mental event), is the essential component of a person, some others argue that body or the physical is the essential constituent of personhood. The third possibility is to talk of person as person, that is, a person as the aggregation of all the components. This third position argues that a person is a whole entity, an indivisible whole. This means that a person cannot be divided into body on one part and mind on the other.
            For those who consider mind, soul, or the mental aspect as the essential element of a person, personal identity requires sameness of consciousness, remembrance or memory. While a variant of this version strictly maintains that sameness of consciousness is all that is required for personal identity, some other variant argues that sameness of consciousness must be conjoined to sameness of body in order to allow for talk of personal identity.
            For the strict memory thesis, personal identity holds and different person-stages belong to the same person if and only if the later could contain an experience which is a memory of a reflective awareness of an experience contained in the earlier.[x] For John Locke, for instance;

  … since consciousness always accompanies thinking and it is that which makes everyone to be what he calls self, and thereby distinguishes himself from all other thinking things: in this alone consists personal identity, i.e.; the sameness of a rational being; and as far as this consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought, so far reaches the identity of that person…[xi]
         
In this passage, Locke makes reflective consciousness the basis for personal identity. By reflective consciousness, Locke meant the conscious act of introspection through which a person critically looks inward and reflects on his or her experiences. For Locke, a person who, through introspection, is able to link the series of experiences at the different levels of his person-stages is identical to the person of the different person-stages.  
          A Quintonian  reformulation of Locke’s memory thesis can be read to mean that there is a sequence of person-stages (not necessarily in the order they occur in time and not excluding repetitions), the first of which is A and the last of which is B, such that each person-stage in the sequence either (i) contains or could contain a memory of an experience contained in the next or (ii) contains an experience of which the next person-stage contains a memory, or could contain a memory.[xii]
           In spite of the criticisms against this thesis on personal identity, the emphasis is on the continuance in the memory chain of experiences attributable to same individual. As this argument goes, personal identity arises when a person at a point in time can link his or her present experience to a whole sequence of past memory chains.
           One problem is that not all philosophers would base personal identity on sameness of memory or consciousness. Some maintain that sameness of consciousness must be conjoined to sameness of body in order to have personal identity. For the proponents of this second view, sameness of consciousness and bodily identity are both important criteria to personal identity. Thus, the argument goes, neither of both can be regarded as the sole criterion of personal identity. It is in line with this view that Sydney Shoemaker maintains that:
… whether or not memory is a criterion of personal identity, it is not the criterion… it cannot be the sole criterion that we use in making identity statements about other persons… Bodily identity is certainly a criterion of personal identity…But I do not think that it can be the sole criterion…[xiii]
      
While these two positions emphasise sameness of consciousness and or bodily identity, there is another position that emphasises the necessary presence of some underlying substances for personal identity to obtain. Yet, some other scholars consider the talk of personal identity a misdirection of energy.[xiv]
         These positions are quite relevant to our discussion of predestination and personal identity. The issue to be examined is whether the chooser or the one who picked the orí in Ìsálú-ọ̀run ( heavenly abode)  is identical to the one who is supposed to be unravelling the destiny here in Ìsálú-ayé (earthly world). The point is that if personal identity between the one who picked an orí in heaven and the person meant to unravel what the orí portends here on earth cannot be established, then, questions about predestination will easily dissolve because there would not be any talk of identity between the two different personalities.
          Looking at the position that emphasizes the significance of an underlying substance in the determination of personal identity, there is the problem of determining what the substance (that which I know not what)[xv] is, or can be taken to mean. If we grant the existence of the substance, there is the problem of how to identify it. Greater still is the problem of using what cannot be identified as the link between one person-stage and the other.
          To serve as a criterion for personal identity, the criterion itself must be identifiable. Since substance, the underlying substratum is something unknowable, or at least, something ‘I know not what’, it cannot be the basis for an empirical question of personal identity. After all, unless we know what the substance is, we would not know whether the different person-stages share the same substance or not. Since sameness must be sameness of something, it stands to reason that the sameness of something ‘I know not what’ cannot be determined, and so unhelpful in the resolution of the problem of personal identity.
         A critical consideration of the problems associated with the earlier accounts of personal identity as discussed within the Western theories, suggests that it may be more productive to explore some Ifá verses to articulate a Yoruba account of the identity of the person who chose an orí, or upon whom an orí was imposed in Ìsálú ọ̀run (heaven). This will enable us address the question of rationality as raised by some anthropologists and philosophers who question the rationality of African beliefs. Perhaps the most influential exponents of the view that African thought system is prelogical, prescientific and unphilosophical were Levy-Bruhl, Rev Fr Placide Tempels, Rev Fr Alexis Kagame, and Robin Horton, among others.16
          These scholars, in different ways, represent the modernist tendency to universalize culture, disregard difference and reduce the specific to the general. For instance, Robin Horton argues that African traditional thought was unphilosophical because it did not meet the analytic ideal of Western philosophy. His conclusion was rested on the misconceptions of philosophy as empirical science and as nothing but logic and epistemology17. The view common to the scholars is that African traditional thought is unphilosophical because (i) it does not meet the analytic ideal of Western philosophy and (ii) it consists of unverifiable statements. This modernist and Universalist approach has been variously tackled by both African and non-African scholars18.
          This paper rejects Horton’s view that adopts analytic rigor and empiricism as the sole standard of Philosophy. The fact that some aspects of African thought consist of unverifiable statements does not make it less philosophical than Metaphysics, existentialism, ethics, and aesthetics. Logical positivism which adopts analytic rigor and empiricism as the sole standard of Philosophy has been variously discredited even by some logical positivists. The lesson from this is that it will be question-begging to use analytic rigor as the telescope and yardstick for measuring the existence and status of African, Oriental, or any non-western thought or philosophy. It cannot be correctly argued that there are any systems of human thought in which the principles of logic are never employed in reasoning, either consciously or unconsciously.     
         The concept of Orí and destiny is well discussed in some chapters and verses of Ifá. The most aptly relevant verses can be found in Ògúndá Méji and Ogbègúndá or Ogbèyọ́nu19. Relevant verses of Ifá give the idea that individual went as a  whole person with a whole body and soul to pick orí. The verses tell of three friends, Oríṣèékú (the son of Ògún), Oríléémèrè (the son of Ija) and Afùwàpẹ́ (the son of Ọ̀rúnmìlà) who were going from heaven to earth to settle down. The account involved sacrifices by Afùwàpé (the son of Ọ̀rúnmìl̀à) before going to pick his orí. As this account goes, this sacrifice aided Afùwàpé’s choice of a good and durable orí which withstood the hazards of the journey to earth and upon which Afùwàpẹ́ became a successful man on earth.
              If this account as recorded by Wande Abimbola (1976) and Bolaji Idowu (1962) is granted, it may be reasonable to assume that a conjunction of sameness of consciousness and sameness of body may be required as criteria for personal identity in Yoruba account of predestination. In other words, the traditional Yoruba account holds that while choosing the destiny or orí in heaven, the individuals were complete beings in terms of the physical body and the mental consciousness. The point then is that in determining the identity of the chooser of orí in Ìsálú ọ̀run and the individual meant to unravel the destiny in Ìsálú ayé, the bodily identity as well as identity of consciousness should be considered.
          This may raise the question of the possibility of bodily existence in ìsálú ọ̀run (heavenly abode), the supposed abode of the spirits. If the individuals in ìsálú ọ̀run were complete human beings, it will be problematic to account for biological processes of conception and stages of foetal developments before the actual birth of human baby. This creates some difficulty for the bodily identity between the chooser of destiny in ìsálú ọ̀run and the one who unravels the destiny here in ìsálú ayé. 
           This shifts the discussion to the realm of consciousness. The question now is whether an identity can be established using the criterion of sameness of consciousness. For those who adopt consciousness as the basis of personal identity, the emphasis is on the capacity to reflectively connect our memory-phases. In other words, personal identity is established between persons P1 and P2 at different times t1 and t2 if P2 at t2 can reflectively call to memory, the experiences of P1 at t1. This, for the consciousness theorists20, is the basis for establishing personal identity.
         The question now is, ‘can the human person, here on earth, whose responsibility it is to unravel the destiny chosen or imposed in heaven, reflectively connect the memory-phases of  the experience of ever choosing a particular kind of orí or destiny in heaven? Unless the person on earth, who is meant to unravel the destiny earlier picked in heaven, can be rationally conscious of, or recall, the memory of the experience of choosing a particular kind of orí in heaven, it will be difficult to say someone on earth chose one destiny or the other in heaven. After all, to talk of a destiny belonging to a particular person is to presuppose that the person to unravel a destiny and the one that picked the destiny both refer to one and the same individual.
          If we go by the position that rests personal identity on consciousness or memory, there is bound to be an initial problem. The initial problem is that it is already contained in the Yoruba account of predestination that the chooser of destiny in ìsálú ọ̀run (heaven) would have passed through or would have crossed the river of forgetfulness while coming to òde-ìsálayé (the human world) and so cannot remember or have a reflective memory of having ever picked an orí.
           The question from this is how to link a destiny to a man who never remembered anything or have been made to forget everything in connection with the destiny or the fact of picking it. If the destiny and its choice are to be of principal relevance to the life of a person, that person must be able to link himself or his life to the destiny and its choice.
          This problem generated by the river of forgetfulness can be adequately taken care of by the Yoruba account according to which Ifá was present at the time when individuals were picking their individual orí21. Based on the supposed presence of Ifá oracle, it is believed that Ifá divination can help to reveal the sort of orí which was chosen and, perhaps, what can be done to change a bad one for good.
           The position assumes the authenticity of Ifá as a plausible means to the knowledge of the transcendent. If this is granted, then, we shall also grant the possibility of linking a person to his destiny through the revelatory knowledge of Ifá oracle. Given this account, it is assumed that anyone who wishes to have his destiny revealed to him would simply seek the assistance of Ifá oracle and its priest. This informs the practice in which the Yoruba consult Ifá at the birth of a new child to know the àkọsẹjáyé; what the future has in stock for the child.
          One problem with this approach is that it does not help the individual concerned to reflectively recollect a forgotten experience. The revealed piece or pieces of information cannot be correctly taken to be a coherent part of a cohesive memory chain. The information from Ifá oracle is extraneous to, and does not form a system with the past and present memory-phases of the individual concerned.
         This can be excused on the point that to insist on the Eurocentric memory-phase argument may be to commit the fallacy of petitio principii or beg the question. After all, the memory-phase argument has its own problems and it is not itself conclusive, final or fool proof. Although the knowledge from Ifá oracle is extraneous, there is no doubt that if Ifá is assumed to have the capacity to make acceptable revelation of the past, it will bridge the gap among different periods of human pasts.
          In spite of this reassuring support from the revelatory prowess of Ifá oracle, its capacity to provide the lost memory of the past can be challenged. For instance, the question of inter-subjective verifiability can be raised. A critic may object that the modus operandi of Ifá as a source of knowledge is not open to the empirical methodology of verification22. It does not allow cross-checking of facts. In fact, two Ifá priests may differ or disagree on what Ifá says about the destiny of a particular individual. The critic may claim further that there is little likelihood, if any, for Ifá to provide the supposed missing link in the memory-phases of a person P1 at t1 who picked an orí, and by extension, destiny, and, the person P2 at t2 who unravels the destiny as encapsulated by the orí.
            This critique of Ifá may be too hasty. The critic may not have sufficiently explored the potentialities or efficacy of Ifá as a means of knowing. The method of Ifá divination should be sufficiently explored. The possible variations that may occur about what Ifá reveals may be due to the variations in the levels of proficiency of different Ifá priests and not necessarily a product of the limitation of Ifá oracle.
            A Yoruba predestinationist may also take relief in the Freudian psycho-analytic theory according to which human consciousness is like an ice-berg on the surface of an ocean. The part beneath the water surface is of greater proportion than the one that is presented to human perception. In other words, the unconscious and the forgotten part of human consciousness are greater in proportion to the conscious part. Moreover, the unconscious libido, to a very noticeable extent, constitutes the basis for human consciousness. Freudian psycho-analysis like Plato’s account of knowledge in Meno23, suggests that an individual would be able to recollect the forgotten part of his consciousness with the aid of serious and methodical questioning.
             The outcome of this is that it would be wrong to deny an individual of the forgotten phase in his memory chain simply because he could no longer recollect such a phase. Moreover, the theory suggests some steps toward recalling such a phase. The question to be raised is whether this Freudian account can help to bridge this missing gap in the Yoruba account of destiny and predestination.
          As interesting as the Freudian argument may seem, it lacks the required strength to solve this problem of destiny and personal identity. It may be interesting to note, for instance, that Freudian psycho-analytic theory does not represent the view of all psychologists. It is difficult to imagine how Freudian psycho-analytic theory or Plato’s idea of knowledge as recollection can help an individual to remember a choice of orí which he ought to have forgotten when crossing the river of forgetfulness before coming to this world24. It will require an infinite number of questioning for someone to recollect experiences which, if ever existed, have been totally erased from the memory chain. On this account, it seems a gratuitous assumption to base a continuity of memory-phase solely on the Freudian psycho-analysis.
          From the foregoing, it can, to a large extent, be argued that an identity cannot be easily established between the agent who picked an orí, and the actual human being who is expected to unravel the destiny which the orí bears. Given the fact that after picking orí, an individual had to be conceived as a foetus before coming to the world, and probably given the uncertainty associated with conception in case of abortion or whatever, it may be too difficult to establish a case of physical continuity or memory sameness between the one who picked an orí and the one who is assumed to be unravelling the destiny. If this identity cannot be established, the idea of predestination may raise a lot of problems. After all, for predestination to be meaningful there must be someone who is predestined. The difficulty in establishing an identity between the person who chose a destiny and the one who is expected to bear the consequences of the destiny makes it difficult or impossible to identify someone with his destiny; and, consequently, makes it difficult to strongly effect any support for the idea of destiny and predestination.
           The idea of destiny and predestination portends some social and moral benefits for the society and the individuals25. One cannot overlook the benefits derived from the idea of predestination in the social and moral spheres of life. There is no doubt that the idea of choice of orí and the destiny it bears has enabled some traditional Yoruba indigenous thinkers to take, with ease, the daily vicissitudes of life and to appreciate and live with the differences in the structure of human existence. Whether or not the choice of orí is true or accepted to be true, the traditional Yoruba believes that he chose an orí, and also that this orí is the bearer of his destiny. While he works hard to realise his destiny, the idea relieves him of the agony of the inequality in the society. The traditional Yoruba respects others and avoids offending others around who may change a good orí to a bad one.
           Nevertheless, as desirable as the idea of predestination may seem, and no matter how reassuring our reasons for desiring predestination may be it does not make predestination real if it is actually not real.

 

Conclusion

This study provides a critical examination of the metaphysical issues of destiny and predestination focusing on the Yoruba account according to which everyone, while in heaven, picked an orí, or found imposed on him, an orí, which encapsulates the successes and failures which the human being is meant to unravel during his course of existence in this world. Proper consideration is given to the social and moral benefits of the notion of predestination in regulating human activities in Yoruba traditional culture. The upshot is that it may be difficult to establish a case of identity between the person who is considered to have chosen a destiny in heaven and the one who is assumed to be unravelling the destiny in this human world.
                Given this difficulty in establishing a relationship of identity between the two personalities, one may conclude that the notion of predestination in general and the Yoruba account in particular, is one of the metaphysical problems that requires more than mere critical argumentation26.









Endnotes
1   See Abimbola Wande, La Notion de Personne en Afrique Noire ( Paris: Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique,1971) No 544,pp73-89, Gbadegesin Olusegun, “Destiny, Personality and the Ultimate Reality of Human Existence: A Yoruba Perspective” in Ultimate Reality and Meaning Vol.7No.3 (1984) :173-188, Makinde M.A., “ An African Concept of Human Personality: The Yoruba Example”  in Ultimate Reality and Meaning Vol. 7 No. 3 (1984): 189-200, Hallen Barry, “ Eniyan: A Critical Analysis of The Yoruba Concepts of Person” in C.S. Momoh (ed.) The Substance of African Philosophy ( Auchi: African Philosophy Projects, 1989) pp328-354, Hallen Barry,  The Good The Bad and The Beautiful: Discourse About Values In Yoruba Culture (Bloomington: Indiana UniversityPress,2000)pp45-46,Sodipo Olubi and Hallen Barry, Knowledge, Belief, and Witchcraft: Analytic Experiments in African Philosophy(London:Ethnographica Publishers,1997)p105,  Salami Yunusa Kehinde, “ Human Personality And Immortality in Traditional Yoruba Cosmology” in Africana Marburgensia XXIV, I, (1991): 4-13, Salami Yunusa Kehinde, “ Human Person, Death, Re-incarnation And Immortality, A Case in Yoruba ( African ) Metaphysics” in ODU: A Journal of West African Studies, 40, ( 2000) : 207-214, among others.

[ii]  Gbadegesin Olusegun, ibid. p.175

[iii]  Idowu Bolaji, Olodumare: God In Yoruba Belief ( London: Longman,1962) pp.170 and 180
[iv]  Ibid.p.183. For more on this, see Morakinyo Olufemi, “ The Ayanmo Myth And Mental Health Care In West Africa “ in Journal Of Culture and Ideas Vol.1 (1983) :68-73
[v] See Idowu Bolaji p.194 and  Salami Yunusa Kehinde ,” Predestination , Freedom, and Responsibility: A Case in Yoruba Moral Philosophy” in  Research in Yoruba Language and Literatures 7 (1996) :6

[vi]Abimbola Wande, Ifa : An Exposition of Ifa Literary Corpus ( Ibadan: Oxford University Press, 1976) p.113

[vii] See Locke John, “ Of Identity and Diversity “ in Woozley A.D. (ed.)  Essay Concerning Human Understanding( London: Fontana Library, 1964) , Quinton Anthony, “ The Soul “ in The Journal  of Philosophy, 59 No.15 (1962), Perry John (ed.) Personal Identity ( Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1975).
[viii]  Reid Thomas, “ Of The Nature and Origin of Our Notion of  Personal Identity “ in Edwards Paul and Pap Arthur (eds.) A Modern Introduction To Philosophy: Readings From Classical and Contemporary Sources ( New York: The Free Press, 1973 ) p.195 
[ix]  Reid Thomas, ibid
[x] See Locke John, “ Of Identity and Diversity”, Quinton Anthony , “ The Soul”, in Perry John(ed) Personal Identity pp3-98
[xi] Locke John, “ Of Identity and Diversity” pp 39-40
[xii] Perry John (ed.) Personal Identity p.19
[xiii] Shoemaker Sydney, “ Personal Identity and Memory” in Perry John (ed.) Personal Identity pp124-129

[xiv]  See Butler Joseph, “ Of Personal Identity” in Perry John, Personal Identity  pp99-105,and Hume David, “ Of  Personal Identity” in Perry John (ed) Personal Identity pp161-172

[xv]   Locke John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (ed.) A. D. Woozley, ( London: Fontana library,1964) pp185-187
16 Tempels Placide, Bantu Philosophy(Paris: Presence Africaine, 1949), Kagame Alexis, Rwandan-Bantu Philosophy of Being(Brussels: Academie Royale des Sciences Coloniales, 1956), Levy-Bruhl Lucian, Notebooks on Primitive Mentality(New York: Harper & Row, 1975), Horton Robin, “African Traditional Thought and Western Science” in Africa Vol.37, Nos.1-2(1967), Horton Robin, Patterns of Thought in Africa and the West: Essays on Magic, Religion and Science(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993)
17 Makinde M. Akin, African Philosophy, Culture, and Traditional Medicine (Athens: Ohio University Centre for International Studies, 1988)p35.
18 Makinde M. Akin, pp35-39, Coetzee P.H and Roux A.P.J.(eds.) The African Philosophy Reader(London: Routledge, 1998) chapter 3, Habermas Jurgen, Post Metaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays(Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1992), Larrain Jorge, Ideology and Cultural Identity: Modernity and the Third World Presence(Cambridge: Polity Press, 1994), Lukes Steven, “Some Problems about Rationality” in Martin Michael and Mclntyre Lee(eds.) Readings in the Philosophy of Social Science(London: MIT Press, 1994)pp285-298, Hallen Barry, A Short History of African Philosophy(Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2002)
19 Abimbola Wande, IFA: An Exposition of Ifa Literary Corpus(Ibadan: Oxford University Press Nigeria, 1976)pp 116-149, Idowu E. Bolaji, Olodumare: God in Yoruba Belief (Ibadan: Longman Nigeria, 1996)pp 179-200
20  See Locke John, “Of Identity and Diversity” in Perry John (ed.) Personal Identity pp33-52, Quinton Anthony, “The Soul” in Perry John, pp53-72, Grice H.P. “Personal Identity” in Perry John, pp73-98
21  Makinde M. Akin, “Ifa as a Repository of Knowledge” in The Proceedings of the 17th World Congress of Philosophy(Montreal: 1983) and Makinde M. Akin, “The Yoruba Concepts of Ori and Human Destiny” in Journal of International Studies in Philosophy(1985): 57
22  While one may not be justified to claim that Science can provide answers to all problems it still behoves us to say that Science has provided the most reliable source of knowledge about the world. In some sense, the disagreement among Ifa Priests may be due to the limitations on the parts of the Priests.
23  See Plato, “Meno”, in Jowett B. (trans.) The Dialogues of Plato Vol. 11 “London: Oxford University Press, 1931), Taylor A.E., Plato: The Man and His Work (Edinburgh: Methuen, 1969), Bedu-Addo J.T., “Sense-Experience and Recollection in Plato’s Meno”, in American Journal of Philology 104(1983):228, Bedu-Addo J.T., “Recollection and the Argument ‘From A Hypothesis’ in Plato’s Meno” in Journal of Hellenic Studies IV(1984):1-14, Gulley N., Plato’s Theory of knowledge(London: Methuen, 1962)pp17-18, Harold Zyskind and Sternfield R.,”Plato’s Meno89c: ‘Virtue is Knowledge’ a Hypothesis?” in Phronesis XXI(1976):130-34, and Freud Sigmund, Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis (New York: W.W. Norton, 1966)
24  There are various hints in Yoruba mythology about how  human beings  were made to forget all that they previously knew in heaven when they passed through the river of forgetfulness just at the boundary between heaven and earth. As the myth goes, once individuals have crossed this river, they are made to forget all they had known earlier in heaven. There are a lot of similarities between this Yoruba account and the accounts of several earlier Greek Philosophers including Plato.
25  Gbadegesin Olusegun, “Destiny, Personality and the Ultimate Reality of Human Existence: A Yoruba Perspective” in Ultimate Reality and Meaning Vol. 7, No.3 (1984): 173-188
26  Critical argumentation is the approach that subjects acceptance or rejection of positions and findings to the merit or demerit of argumentative reasoning devoid of emotions and personal subjective feelings. Critical argumentation presupposes that no position is accepted unless it is supported with adequate and convincing reasoning.

References
Abimbola Wande 1976. Ifa: An Exposition of Ifa Literary Corpus, Ibadan: Oxford University Press.
Abimbola Wande 1971. La Notion de Personne en Afrique Noire, Paris: Centre National de la  Recherche Scientifique.
Bedu-Addo J.T. 1984. "Recollection and the Argument from 'A Hypothesis' in Plato's 'Meno'"  in Journal of Hellenic Studies IV : 1-14.
Coetzee P.H., and Roux A.P.J. 1988. (eds.) The African Philosophy Reader, London: Routledge.
Edwards P. and Pap A.1973. (eds.) A Modern Introduction to Philosophy: Readings From Classical and Contemporary Sources, New York: The Free Press.
Freud S.1966. Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, New York: W.W. Norton.
Gbadegesin O.1984. "Destiny, Personality and the Ultimate Reality of Human Existence: A Yoruba Perspective" in Ultimate Reality and Meaning Vol.7, No. 3: 173-188
Gulley N.1962. Plato's Theory of Knowledge, London: Methuen.
Habermas J.1991. Post Metaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays, Massachusetts: MIT Press,
Hallen B.2002. A Short History of African Philosophy, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Hallen B. 1989. "Eniyan: A Critical Analysis of the Yoruba Concepts of Person" in Momoh C.S. (ed.) The Substance of African Philosophy, Auchi: African Philosophy Projects, pp.328-354.
Hallen B. 2000. The Good The Bad and The Beautiful:Discourse about Values in Yoruba Culture,  Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Harold Z. and Sternfield R.1976. "Plato's Meno 89c: 'Virtue is Knowledge' a hypothesis" in Phronesis Vol.xxi : 130-134
Horton R. 1976. "African traditional Thought and Western Science" in African Vol. 37, Nos. 1-2.
Horton R.1993. Patterns of Thought in Africa and the West: Essays on Magic, Religion and Science Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Idowu B. 1962. Olodumare: God in Yoruba Belief, London: Longman.
Jowett B. 1931. (Trans.) The Dialogues of Plato Vol. 11, London: Oxford University Press.
Kagame A.1956. Rwandan-Bantu Philosophy of Being, Brussels: Academic Royale des Sciences.
Larrain J.1994. Ideology and Cultural Identity: Modernity and the Third world Presence,
            Cambridge: Polity Press.
Levy-Bruhl Lucian1975 Notebooks on Primitive Mentality, New York: Harper and Row.
Locke J. 1964. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Woozley A.D. (ed.), London: Fontana Llibrary.
Makinde M.A. 1983. "Ifa as a Repository of Knowledge" in The Proceedings of the 17th World Congress of Philosophy, Montreal.
Makinde M.A. 1985."The Yoruba Concepts of Ori and Human Destiny" in The Journal of International Studies in Philosophy.
Makinde M.A.1988. "African Philosophy, Culture and Traditional Medicine, Athens: Ohio University Centre for International Studies.
Martin M., and Maclntyre L. 1991. (eds) Readings in the Philosophy of Social Science, London: MIT Press.
Morakinyo O.1983. "The Ayanmo Myth and Mental Health Care in West Africa" in Journa of Culture and Ideas Vol.1:68-73
Perry J. 1975. (ed.) Personal Identity, Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Quinton A., "The Soul" in Journal of Philosophy, Vol.59, No.15 (1962)
Salami Y.K. 1991. "Human Personality and Immortality in Traditional Yoruba Cosmology",  in Africana Marburgensia, Vol.24, No.1:4-13
Salami Y.K., 1996. "Predestination, Freedom and Responsibility: A case in Yoruba Moral Philosophy" in Research in Yoruba Language and Literatures, Vol.7.
Salami Y.K.2000. " Human Person,Death, Reincarnation and Immortality: A Case in Yoruba (African) Metaphysics" in ODU: A Journal of West African Studies, Vol.40: 207-214
Sodipo O. and Hallen B. 1997. Knowledge, Belief and Witchcraft: Analytic Experiments in African Philosophy: London: Ethnographica Publishers,1997
Taylor A.E.1969. Plato: the Man and His Work, Edinburgh: Methuen.
Tempels P. 1949. Bantu Philosophy, Paris: Presence Africaine.
         

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

YORÙBÁ LITERATURE E-LIBRARY

SYNTAX AND GRAMMATICAL THEORIES E-LIBRARY SECTION

YORÙBÁ GRAMMAR E-LIBRARY SECTION